Japanese

May 29, 1999

Time:
3:00pm, May 29, 1999
Place:
Room L-620, 6th floor, Central Library, Sophia University.
Speaker:
Toshiyuki Ogihara (University of Washington/Kanda University of International Studies)
Title:
A Scope Theory of Tense and Adnominal Modifiers
Abstract:
A Scope Theory of Tense and Adnominal Modifiers

This paper defends a scope theory of tense, according to which 
tense morphemes systematically determine the temporal 
interpretations of the expressions that occur in structurally 
lower positions. The evidence for this view comes from the 
behavior of adnominal modifiers (present and past participles, in 
particular) in English. For example, it is virtually impossible to 
interpret (1a) to mean that the man who was singing on the stage 
is now drinking wine. On the other hand, (1b) is interpreted to 
mean that the man who was singing on the stage was smiling at 
Mary (simultaneously). In (1a-b) the temporal interpretation of 
the present participle is determined the tense. On the other hand, 
the fact that (1c) is acceptable is accounted for in terms of QR.

(1)     a.      # The man singing on the stage is now drinking wine.
        b.      The man singing on the stage was smiling at Mary.
        c.      The man singing on the stage (now) was a car 
                salesman before.

At first sight, this proposal appears to go against the view 
that temporal properties of common nouns cannot be accounted 
for in terms of a scope theory of tense (e.g., Enc (1981, 1986), 
Musan (1995)). For example, Enc (1981) presents examples like (2) 
to show that the temporal interpretation of the common noun 
fugitive is not determined by the tense morpheme.

(2)     a.      Every fugitive is now in jail.
        b.      There were many homeless people at the rally.

The most natural interpretation of (2a) is that every person who 
was a fugitive in the past is now in jail. However, there is no 
tense morpheme that could be responsible for the temporal 
location of fugitive, which is a past interval. Enc accounts for 
this fact by assuming that nouns (and also verbs) are indexicals 
and that they are not operators. Musan (1995) modifies Enc's 
proposal and accounts for "temporally dependent reading" of 
nouns such as (2b) in terms of the idea that determiners quantify 
over stages of individuals. Musan argues with Enc, however, that 
the data cannot be explained in terms of scope.

Our position with respect to common nouns is that they are 
inherently very different from verbs or adjectives in that they 
have their own mechanism for determining their temporal 
properties. The exact characterization of such mechanism is 
beyond the scope this paper, but we adopt Enc's indexical analysis 
of nouns for simplicity. The important point here is that adopting 
this proposal does not necessarily mean that we should or must 
dispense with a scope theory of tense. If the temporal argument 
of a common noun is a free variable, then its interpretation is not 
affected by tense even if tense has scopal properties. Thus, a 
scope analysis of tense is at least harmless as far as common 
nouns are concerned. Given examples like (1a-c), we now have 
reason to hypothesize that tense does determine temporal 
interpretations of structurally lower expressions. Thus, a scope 
analysis of tense is necessary.

There may possibly be cases in which the temporal properties 
of adnominal modifiers cannot be explained in terms of scope 
alone. For instance, (3a) may be marginally acceptable on the 
interpretation in which the people in question were fugitives and 
were crying for joy at some past time. However, even if this were 
granted, (3b) could not possibly mean that the current professor 
who used to cry at home when she was waiting for her parents 
(when she was a little child) has three children now.

(3)     a.      ?? Every fugitive crying for joy is now in jail.
        b.      # The professor crying at home waiting for her 
                parents has three children now.

This means that the temporal interpretation of an adnominal 
modifier is determined in terms of scope, with the possible 
exception of some marginal cases in which it harmonizes with 
the temporal interpretation of its modifiee. This proposal agrees 
with Ogihara (1996), who argues for the same view based 
primarily upon the behavior of Japanese relative clauses.
In sum, we need to adopt a scope theory of tense to account for 
temporal properties of adnominal modifiers because they are 
structure dependent. The known behavior of common nouns should 
be explained in terms an independent mechanism, but not by 
rejecting a scope analysis of tense.

Selected References
Enc, Murvet (1981) Tense without Scope, Ph.D. dissertation, 
University of Wisconsin-Madison.
Enc, Murvet (1986) "Towards a Referential Analysis of Temporal 
Expressions," Linguistics and Philosophy 9, 405-426.
Musan, Renate (1995) On the Temporal Interpretation of Noun 
Phrases, Ph.D. dissertation, MIT.
Ogihara, Toshiyuki (1996) Tense, Attitudes, and Scope, Kluwer, 
Dordrecht.


Last modified: Sun May 23 18:33:16 JST 1999